Response to David Coady's “An Epistemic Defence of the Blogosphere”
Preamble/vocab for non-philosophers:
I wrote this for a class so, although I've tried to avoid it as much as possible, there are a few technical words which I'll explain here:
Epistemic reliability: A source is epistemically reliable if it produces/conveys more true beliefs than false beliefs. Epistemic just means having to do with knowledge.
Knowledge that is vertistic: knowledge as true belief.
I think that's it!
I wrote this for a class so, although I've tried to avoid it as much as possible, there are a few technical words which I'll explain here:
Epistemic reliability: A source is epistemically reliable if it produces/conveys more true beliefs than false beliefs. Epistemic just means having to do with knowledge.
Knowledge that is vertistic: knowledge as true belief.
I think that's it!
Intro
“.
. . [W]henever the people are well-informed, they can be trusted with
their own government; that, whenever things get so far wrong as to
attract their notice, they may be relied on to set them right."
(Padover, 1939, p. 88). The implication here is the widely shared
belief that a well-functioning democracy isn't possible without the
public knowing what's going on in their government. Of course, this
assumes that the information the public receives is likely to be
true, which in turn depends on the reliability of the sources from
which it is acquired by the public.
In
the internet age, the blogosphere has emerged as a popular source for
political news and commentary. Given its rise in popularity it's
worthwhile considering its epistemic benefits relative to those of
the conventional media and whether the blogosphere positively
contributes to our democratic practices. Goldman (2008) takes the
negative view arguing that the blogosphere is a less reliable source
of information than the conventional media and therefore does not benefit our democratic practices. In “An Epistemic
Defence of the Blogosphere,” David Coady argues for
the positive position and
counters Goldman's three main lines of argument against the epistemic
reliability of the blogosphere (relative to that of the conventional
media). Coady argues contra
Goldman that the blogosphere (a) doesn't undermine professional
journalism, (b) doesn't lack balance in any detrimental way, and (c)
isn't parasitic on the conventional media. Finally, Coady concludes
that the blogosphere benefits our epistemic well-being and improves
our democratic practices.
I will briefly outline Coady's main argument then I will argue that both Goldman and Coady are mistaken to focus their attention on evaluating the relative epistemic reliability of the blogosphere because (a) no meaningful distinction can be made in terms of reliability and (b) whatever current distinction there is will likely soon evaporate. I conclude that (c) even if we assume that one or the other class of media is more reliable this doesn't matter one fig given the wide range of reliability within each class; what matters is whether the citizenry is able to distinguish between good and bad arguments and good and bad sources. A citizenry with low cognitive abilities will easily be mislead by the sensational and find themselves sucked into epistemic black holes--despite the existence of some reliable sources, conventional or otherwise.
I will briefly outline Coady's main argument then I will argue that both Goldman and Coady are mistaken to focus their attention on evaluating the relative epistemic reliability of the blogosphere because (a) no meaningful distinction can be made in terms of reliability and (b) whatever current distinction there is will likely soon evaporate. I conclude that (c) even if we assume that one or the other class of media is more reliable this doesn't matter one fig given the wide range of reliability within each class; what matters is whether the citizenry is able to distinguish between good and bad arguments and good and bad sources. A citizenry with low cognitive abilities will easily be mislead by the sensational and find themselves sucked into epistemic black holes--despite the existence of some reliable sources, conventional or otherwise.
Outline
of Coady's Argument:
(P1)
Although the blogosphere might undermine professional journalism, it
doesn't follow that it harms the “epistemic prospects” of the
citizenry because political questions shouldn't be the exclusive
domain of experts--we ought also appeal to 'the wisdom of the crowds'
(i.e., bloggers).
(P2) The conventional media's ostensible virtue of balance actually excludes genuine balance because it omits points of view that aren't those of the dominant parties. The blogosphere, on the other hand, can accommodate every micro-perspective. This is an epistemic benefit to the citizenry.
(P3) Despite Goldman's argument that the blogosphere isn't independent from the conventional media, the dependance relation also runs the other way. The conventional media often turns to blogs as sources because blogs can do things the conventional media can't or doesn't do (like close examination of public documents, in depth analysis, etc...). These activities, which are most typical to the blogosphere, are an epistemic benefit to the citizenry.
(C) It follows from (P1), (P2), and (P3) that the blogosphere provides an epistemic benefit to the citizenry because it does things that the conventional media can't or doesn't do much of.
(P2) The conventional media's ostensible virtue of balance actually excludes genuine balance because it omits points of view that aren't those of the dominant parties. The blogosphere, on the other hand, can accommodate every micro-perspective. This is an epistemic benefit to the citizenry.
(P3) Despite Goldman's argument that the blogosphere isn't independent from the conventional media, the dependance relation also runs the other way. The conventional media often turns to blogs as sources because blogs can do things the conventional media can't or doesn't do (like close examination of public documents, in depth analysis, etc...). These activities, which are most typical to the blogosphere, are an epistemic benefit to the citizenry.
(C) It follows from (P1), (P2), and (P3) that the blogosphere provides an epistemic benefit to the citizenry because it does things that the conventional media can't or doesn't do much of.
It
Don't Mean Stink if You Don't Know How to Think
Instead of focusing on the central argument I will attempt to make the case that this debate over the relative epistemic benefits of the blogosphere and conventional media, while interesting, is of minimal importance. If our chief concern is epistemic well-being and good democratic decision-making, what really matters is the general level of critical thinking in the citizenry. An important part of the debate between Goldman and Coady hinges upon there being a meaningful distinction between journalists in the conventional media and bloggers. To begin making my case, I'll try to show that this distinction cannot be sustained.
Instead of focusing on the central argument I will attempt to make the case that this debate over the relative epistemic benefits of the blogosphere and conventional media, while interesting, is of minimal importance. If our chief concern is epistemic well-being and good democratic decision-making, what really matters is the general level of critical thinking in the citizenry. An important part of the debate between Goldman and Coady hinges upon there being a meaningful distinction between journalists in the conventional media and bloggers. To begin making my case, I'll try to show that this distinction cannot be sustained.
Coady
gives several criteria to mark the distinction:
(a) Journalists are paid while bloggers
are not; (b) journalists are part an institution and therefore
subject to institutional norms (for better or for worse) while
bloggers are not; (c) journalists have access to “the halls of
power” to collect information while bloggers' principle form of
research consists in close examination of publicly available
documents; (d) journalists have their information filtered in a way
that bloggers don't.
With the exception of perhaps (d), I
suggest that these criteria do not establish a strong demarkation
between the two categories because there are many obvious
counter-examples to each of the criteria. Regarding (a), many
bloggers are well-paid and make a living off of sponsorships and ads.
In fact, many bloggers aspire to this. Regarding (b), many academics
and professionals have blogs. When they blog in their capacity as
academic and professional, just like journalists they are also
subject to strong professional and institutional truth-telling norms,
in these cases do they suddenly cease to be bloggers? That's
unlikely. Coady himself gives a counter-example to (c), and
presumably as individual blogs grow their audience and opinion-making
power, this distinction will be obliterated. Access to the halls of
power is a poor demarkation criteria.
The last criteria is (d) is perhaps
the most promising as a demarkation criterion. The concentration of
corporate power and friendly ties to those in power suggest that the
conventional media is subject to a type of filtering to which blogs
are not. That said, as Coady himself indicates, there are examples
of bloggers also gaining face-to-face access to politicians. It's
not unreasonable to suspect this access is because of their favorable
disposition or reluctance to criticize the particular politician;
i.e., filtering similar to that in the conventional media. Of
course, the bloggers are not subject to institutionally-imposed
filtering norms, nevertheless it seems that anyone who's going to get
face-to-face access—blogger and journalist--gets that access on the
precondition of at least some filtering. One would presume that as
individual blogs increase their audience and clout so too will their
possibility of access increase, in turn further blurring the line
between blogger and journalist. The point here is simply that in the
long run this demarkation criteria probably going to grow
increasingly porous and so isn't going to succeed in drawing a clear
line.
Recall why we even care about
marking a distinction between the two categories of media. We want
to know if the blogosphere is a net benefit for a democracy in terms
of its ability to reliably provide true information to the citizenry
which will in turn cash out as a benefit to good democratic
decision-making. Now, suppose one were to reject my above arguments
against a meaningful demarkation, I believe I can still make my case
against it: For each category the range of reliability is so wide as
to make any meaningful distinction irrelevant in terms of the
property we care about: reliability. In sum, the degree to which the
two categories (if we presuppose some essential difference) overlap
in terms of reliability renders them indistinguishable from each
other in this respect.
Consider the conventional media.
Who's in this category? Fox News, MSNBC, CBC, CBS, ABC, CNN,
Huffington Post, NYT, NPR, PRI, and PBS to name a few. In terms of
reliability, anyone who's bothered to look at recent media studies
literature will tell you that there's a huge gap between the
reliability of say, Fox News and NPR. For example, in several polls
testing knowledge of current events, Fox News viewers scored even
lower those who don't follow the news (citation). Not surprisingly,
the more ideological the news source (regardless of ideology), the
worse the participants' knowledge of current events. The group who
scored best were those who listened to NPR.
So what's my point besides the fact
that everyone should donate and listen to NPR? The point is that in
terms of reliability—the property with which are concerned—the
range within the category “conventional media” is so wide such
that ascribing a reliability score to the category is rendered
meaningless. “Conventional Media” captures pretty much any
reliability value you choose, depending on the case you're trying to
make.
It should come as no surprise that the
same argument can be made of the blogosphere. From Alex Jones' Info
Wars and the rest of the wacky wonderworld of
conspiracy-of-everything blogs to blogs run by elite Ivy League
professors, the range of reliability within the blogosphere is
vast. The distribution is so wide that to speak of “the
reliability of the blogosphere” is essentially meaningless—even
more so than for the conventional media. You can make the
reliability score fit whatever position you wish to support depending
on the cluster of blogs you select.
Essentially, you can pick and choose a
conventional source and a blog to make whatever case you want about
the relative reliability of each category. One reply might be to
average the reliability over all prototypical members of the class
but this would do no more than distort what we really want to know:
If a citizen gets their news from blogs or conventional media, which
one is more likely to reliably report true beliefs? It all depends
on which particular source of
conventional media we are talking about and which particular blogs
she chooses. It'll return to this later.
There are further reasons to be
skeptical of any attempt to meaningfully distinguish and make
pronouncements about the conventional media and the blogosphere in
terms of reliability. Consider
a hypothetical situation where there's no blogosphere and only
conventional media. Is the conventional media reliable? That is,
does it announce more true information than false? It depends. Do
we live in North Korea? Or do we live in a Western democracy with
strong laws protecting freedom of the press and a low concentration
of media ownership? Or do we live somewhere in between? The point
here is that there's nothing intrinsically reliable about
conventional media. It's reliability is contingent upon many
variables many of which are political, legal, and economic. With
this in mind, lets return to the central issue: Does the conventional
media improve our democratic practices (via epistemic benefits)? The
answer and reasons are same as for the reliability question: it
depends.
How
about if we consider a population where there is only a blogosphere
and no conventional media. Is the blogosphere more reliable? Again,
it depends. What blogs is a person reading? How are they choosing
what blogs they read? Do they pick blogs that confirm their
pre-existing ideological biases or do they actively seek out blogs that challenge
their point of view? The empirical evidence suggests the former.
The
wide and overlapping distributions of reliability within and between
the blogosphere and the conventional media as well as the contingent
nature of each categories' reliability score all suggest that the
reliability issue is of only minimal significance. To true see why
lets return to the issue that motivated the whole project to begin
with: how can we best ensure that the public is well-informed such
that our democratic practices are improved? Coady would have us
believe that there mere fact that people have access to a range of
positions where they will encounter mutually incompatible points of
view implies that “as a result they are able to develop their
critical faculties, which in turn helps them make better choices
about what and whom to believe” (p. 291).
Unfortunately
for Coady, there are journals replete with literature to the
contrary. I wish I could share his optimism, but exposure to a plurality of
views isn't sufficient if we don't take into account the various
conditions under which these views are encountered. For example,
consider level of education. The Dunning-Kruger effect shows that
those least able to reason are most confident in their ability to do
so and most recalcitrant to correction. Johnathan Haidt's research
shows that we are recalcitrant to facts that undercut cherished
beliefs. Kahan's research shows that our ideological biases
determine who we consider to be an expert. The backfire-effect
(Brendan Nyhan and Jason Reifler) shows that in the face of strong
disconfirming evidence people will further entrench their beliefs rather than align them with new and better evidence.
Even something as objective as doing basic math is distorted by our
political biases (Kahan) and the effect is stronger with
numeracy! There's also a growing body of literature on how people
make media choices and it doesn't support Coady's hypothesis: the
majority of the population chooses its media sources based on whether
it confirms their existing views. Most people want confirmation and
comfort rather than the discomfort of cognitive dissonance when their
cherished beliefs and values are challenged.
There
are too many studies to list here but the upshot is that (a)
encountering disconfirming views on its own is unlikely to confer any
epistemic benefit and, even if this weren't the case, (b) the vast
majority seek out sources which confirm rather than challenge their
views essentially sending them into an epistemic echo chamber. For example, the
literature on conspiracy theorists is clear. Anyone who enters
this epistemic black hole has little chance of ever escaping: any
evidence against the conspiracy is counted as evidence for it.
“With
the click of a mouse, you enter the world of conspiracism, and you
never have to leave that world,” the University of Utah's Goldberg
explained. “You get a situation where you are confirmed, and you
don’t have any information that advises you to look in a different
direction ... There’s an inner core of people who are committed.”
And not only are these people
stuck in a feedback loop of confirmation bias and groupthink, but
they are actually being radicalized in the process as well, Goldberg
maintained.1
Given massive cuts to education, emphasis on rote learning for standardized tests and its consequences to the critical thinking skills of the general populous, its hard to see how the rise of the conspiratorial and sensational in the blogosphere should be counted as epistemic gain.
The
obvious reply is that I am committing the fallacy of confirming
instances for surely there are also blogs that are extremely
vertistic. True, but there are several confounding factors. First
of all, as I've mentioned already, given the human propensity to
seek confirmation we should expect that these “good” blogs will
be ignored by those who could most benefit from them. Second, I'd
wager the conspiratorial, sensationalist, and ideological blogs as a
whole have way more traffic than the reliable blogs and that there's
little overlap between the audiences. Finally, for those that enter
the blogosphere neutral, the gravitational force of the “bad” type
of blog is much stronger than that of the “good” type.
So,
what are we to make of this mess? Is there any way to draw a
meaningful distinction between the blogosphere and the conventional
media? I'm not sure but if there is
any thing distinctive about the blogosphere it is that its possible
range of epistemic reliability is wider than that of the conventional
media. Conversely, at least in most Western democracies, there are institutional
norms that prevent chronic outright fabrication in the conventional
media. To be fair, Coady acknowledges as much when he marks the
distinction between the epistemic virtues of avoiding false beliefs
and acquiring true beliefs. The conventional media might win out
over the blogosphere in achieving the former.
Lets
return once again to the motivating issue. To the extent that we can
even talk about the blogosphere and the conventional media as
distinct categories and given the overlapping wide-ranges of
reliability values between and within each class, can anything be said about the
blogosphere in respect to its role in a democracy? To answer this,
let me once again quote Padover: "If a nation expects to be
ignorant and free, in a state of civilization, it expects what never
was and never will be." (1939, p. 89). In other words, the
blogosphere is only a benefit from an epistemic point of view if
people have the requisite critical thinking skills such that they can
distinguish between good and bad sources and good and bad arguments.
Blogs,
like many tools, are proverbial double-edged swords. Some are more
epistemically reliable than the best “conventional” news source
and some are so epistemically naughty it would make Fox News blush.
For the citizen who has the cognitive tools to critically evaluate
the quality of sources or luckily stumbles on a network of credible
blogs, blogs are a net epistemic benefit. For someone who tumbles
down the rabbit whole of conspiracy or strongly ideological blogs,
they are not likely to again see the light of reason. The same sword
that defends you from harm can also cut you. It depends on the skill of
he who wields it.
1
Anatomy of a Conspiracy Theorist. March 15, 2013.
http://www.ibtimes.com/anatomy-conspiracy-theorist-inside-new-wave-ancient-tradition-1127679
No comments:
Post a Comment