In this blog I present, in an informal way, core ideas in philosophy and their application to current events and everyday life. For critical thinking lessons and resources, please check out my free online course reasoningforthedigitalage.com
Mill's Utilitarianism, Chapter IV: Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility is Susceptible
Note: For criticisms of Mill's Proof see my later posts "Sidgwick's Criticisms of Mill's Proof" and "Moore's Criticisms of Mill's Proof"
Favorite Quote: "...[Virtue] may be felt a good in itself, and desired as such with as great intensity as any other good; and with these differences between it and the love of money, of power, or of fame--that all of these may, and often do, render the individual noxious to the other members of society to which he belongs, whereas there is nothing which makes him so much a blessing to them as the cultivation of the disinterested love of virtue." Background A familiar theme in many branches of philosophy (mostly epistemology) is how to prove a primitive. By "primitive", I mean a foundational fact. A fact that to the question "why?" you can't reply anymore than "it just is". Think of it this way: Imagine you're taking to a really annoying kid who keeps asking "why" to every successive answer you give. At some point, you're going to run out of answers. Or punch him right in the face!!
Here's an example of a conversation reaching a primitive (from a criminally underrated comedy): Example of an Epistemic Primitive(video) So, what's all the hoopla about primitives? Well, Mill has a problem with proving utilitarianism because it is claimed that its first principle (ie. an action is good to the degree that it maximizes happiness for the greatest number of peeps) is a primitive. But so are the first principles of any moral system. If proponents of each moral system each tell me I should accept their particular first principle because "it just is the right one", why should I choose one system over another? And on what grounds? Mill recognizes this problem and tries to give us a proof... Proof of Happiness as the Only Good We begin with what Mill sets out to prove: that in human affairs, happiness is the only desirable end. Not that we don't want other things, but that we want other things like money, honor, success, friends, and family because they are often only means to our ultimate end, which is happiness. But why should we agree with this? First argument: How do we know if something is visible? People see it. How do we know if something is audible? People hear it. So...how do we know if something is desirable? You got it...people desire it! Ok, so people desire their own happiness perhaps, but it doesn't necessary follow that people desire the happiness of others... Baaaat! That's not what we're trying to prove. We're not primarily concerned with what people actually do, we are concerned with defining what moral goodness is. The fact that a person values and desires their own happiness tells us that happiness is a good to that person. So, the general happiness must be a good to the aggregate of all persons. So far we've (more or less) established that happiness is a good because it is the desired end of most people's actions, but we have yet to establish that it is the only good. To do this we have to demonstrate that happiness is the only thing that people desire. It seems clear that there are other things people desire such as virtue (some people), absence of pain, and absence of vice, makin' paypur, range rovers, etc... So, how does Mill argue for his postion? He could say that all the other things people desire are instrumental ends; that is, they are merely a means to happiness. But no, that'd be a cheap move and open him to some easy challenges. Instead, he pursues a slightly different (but similar) strategy. He acknowledges that for some people, they actually do pursue virtue, money, fame, etc... not as means to happiness but as ends in themselves. So, how is that consistent with happiness being the only ultimate end? The answer is that although people might not pursue virtue and such as a means to happiness, but as a component of happiness. Huh? Wut? How does this work? Lets drawr an analogy with money. Most people pursue money as a means to some end. People pursue money cuz it will get them the things they really want. In the standard case, money is an instrumental end. It is simply an intermediary step on the way to getting what we really want. But, sometimes, in the course of some people's lives, they start to want money just to have it. They don't use it to get other things. They want money for money's sake. They like to love it and feed it and pet it...This is usually a progression. It doesn't happen over night. Not that it would matter if it did. The point is, that somewhere along the line some people pursue money just to have money. Having the money--by itself--makes them feel happy. Ok, lets go back to virtue. Most people typically act virtuously because helping other people makes them feel good. If they didn't get a good feeling from acting virtuously, they might not so act. But, hopefully, some people over time will start to value acting virtuously just for the sake of it. Why? Because this has become an element in the set of things that make them happy. Being virtuous makes them happy. Just like simply having money makes some people happy. The difference is subtle. In the first instance we are virtuous, not because we have a desire to be virtuous, but because acting so will afford us some pleasure; that is, we seek the consequence of 'pleasure' from the consequence of our virtuous act. Over time, acting virtuously itself becomes a source of pleasure. We get a warm fuzzy feeling from helping people. What kind of people? People that need help! And so, virtue becomes a component of what is considered to be pleasure/happiness. It gets included in the umbrella of things we equate with happiness, and thus, "good". I have to admit, I find this a little sophistic. Here's another quick example that might make strengthen Mill's case. Few people listen to music because they figure the end result of doing so will bring them happiness. Instead, for many people music is an element in set of things that are happiness, thus becoming a good in itself. Music is happiness--or at least listening to it is. And being virtuous (for some) is a direct source of happiness. Acting virtuously is simply included in that person's definition of what it means to be happy. So, because things like music and virtue, in themselves, come to cause us happiness, they become goods in themselves. But why are these things goods? Because they produce happiness...Ah ha! So, you see...we've come full circle: that which brings about happiness is good--be it virtue or music, and whether we seek it as a means or an end! And what's more, this proves what we've been trying to prove all along, that "there is in reality nothing desired except happiness." It's an interesting thought experiment to come up with a counter example. Is it possible that someone would listen to music if they thought it would make them unhappy? That's probably a bad attempt at a counterexample. Lets ax instead if it's possible that someone would act virtuously if they expected it to make them unhappy. Possibly. But the utilitarian would reply that the arbiter of goodness isn't a particular individual's happiness but the total happiness produced. So, we need to re-ax the quextion: (Hai! Ya!) Would someone self-sacrifice if they knew that it wouldn't increase the happiness of others or at least prevent their suffering? On what grounds would they be acting? I suppose it's possible but it certainly would appear strange. Not that humans don't already engage in a crap load of strange behaviours. But I digress... So where we at? Oh right. Proving that happiness is the only thing that human's desire. Why is happiness the only thing humans desire? Because the ends of our actions are all either directed at something that we consider to be part of happiness or a means to happiness. Now here's the part that's a little sketchy. The first premise we've established is that (1) The only thing that humans want is things that are a part of happiness or are a means to happiness. From this it follows that (2) these are the only desirable things. The next premise I'm not sure where it came from, he just kind of sneaks it in: (3) "the promotion of happiness is the test by which to judge all human conduct." Then Mill concludes (C) "it necessarily follows that it must be the criterion of morality, since a part is included in the whole." What I don't see is where (3) comes from. It looks like it's supposed to follow from (1) and (2), but there is no logical connection as far as I can tell. What er'body wants and the benchmark for evaluating the moral worth of actions are not necessarily connected. As a "gentle" Christian once told me, "children in hell want ice water." Doesn't mean the standard of conduct should be measured by how much ice water is produced... The obvious response is to ax why they wanted ice water: to bring them relief from suffering (same as pleasure/happiness for a utilitarian). So, check mate! Utilitarians win again. Mill would probably futher respond that, "you dumbass, we've just spend a crap load of ink and paper proving what 'good' is. 'Good' is whatever produces happiness. More happiness= more better. So, a good (i.e., morally right) action is one that produces the most happiness for the greatest amount of peeps. Eazy peezy japonese-y! Happiness is goodness! That's what good is! And there is only one good--happiness. Were you asleep or something?" Or something like that. He could be quite short with people that questioned him. That's all for tonight. I hope this made you happy...meaning it was good!
Yo check it. Weez about to learn about why (Mill thinks) we should be compelled to adopt and adhere to utilitarianism as the ultimate moral standard. That is, why does a utilitarian ethic have binding force? Overview and RecapOk, so...like...'member utilitarianism? It's the idear that the moral goodness of an action is proportional to the total amount of happiness (or pleasure) it produces (for the agent as well as--and especially--other people). So, an action that produces more pleasure/happiness for 5 people is more gooder than an action that produces pleasure/happiness for only 1. Simple enough so far, right? (We'll table some of the problems to get to the point of this post.) Next step--Definition: Happiness and pleasure are one and the same for utilitarians so I'll just say happiness to mean both; happiness also includesavoidance of pain. But Mill makes a distinction between types of pleasure: higher (intellectual) and lower (sensual). We know some pleasures to have more worth than others because the majority of peeps who experience and have the capacity for both will choose the higher over the lower. Ok, supposing we accept everything so far, there's still a prollem--why should I be motivated to obey this standard of morality? What's stopping me from being a selfish egotistical misanthrope and stepping on others to feed my own ravenous appetite for pleasure? That's the problem Mill tackles in this section... Of the Ultimate Sanction of the Principle of Utility People Will Act on Utilitarian Principles Because They Already Are UtilitariansThe general gist of Mill's argument for why we should be motivated to obey the utilitarian maxim and whence it derives its motivating force is that we are already utilitarians and this is the natural moral position! Of course he has some more specific arguments to support this assertion which we will look at... Mill sets things up for his we're-utilitarian-even-if-we-don't-know-it view like this: Many people recognize a moral duty not to murder, steal, and deceive yet might question the utilitarian maxim to act according to what will promote the general happiness. How do we explain the feeling of moral duty toward abstaining from these specific acts while there is no corresponding feeling to act on the utilitarian maxim? Mill suggests that we have accepted the specific consequences of utilitarianism but not the general maxim. But this failure is simply a consequence of poor education and lack of influences which form moral character. If people got their learn on, the 1st principle of utilitarianism "shall be as deeply rooted in our character, and to our own consciousness as completely a part of our nature, as the horror of crime is in an ordinarily well-bought up young person." Basically, people who accept the consequences of the utilitarian ethic but not its principle do so because it falls outside oftheir particular custom and education--and so they question it. But this is nothin' a little learnin' can't fix. The obvious problem with this argument is that it can be made by any ethical system. Hey, if you raise everyone as Kantians and teach them to see the moral truth in Kantianism, chances are, the majority will think the categorical imperative (one should only act according to principles that you'd want everyone to act on) is the one true moral principle. Actually, if you ax most 'mericans (Republicans, anyway) they'll probably advocate an egoist morality; that is, since people are rational and self-interested, actions that are in line with the principle of rational self-interest are 'right'--provided another's rights aren't infringed upon. If only they knew they are really just misguided utilitarians... Anyhow, what really jumps out at me is how Aristotelian Mill sounds wilt all this moral education stuff. Aristotle basically said (super condensed version), an action is good if it is by a virtuous person and a virtuous person is one who has had a correct moral education. In a way, Mills just adding on that someone with the correct moral education would act according to the utilitarian principle. Sanctions Recall that the whole point of this section of the utilitarian argument is to defend utilitarianism from critics who charge that utilitarianism can't work because there's no reason for people to go along with it. In this context, Mill discusses external and internal sanctions that may or may not compel someone to act according to the utilitarian ethic. Regarding external sanctions he says they are the same for any possible moral system: desire to be praised and avoid punishment (earthly or cosmic). Lets move on to internal sanctions... Internal SanctionsSo, what is it that might compel us to consider our action's effect on the general good above all other considerations? What is it that makes us feel as though we have a duty to consider the general good? It is "a feeling in the mind; a pain, more or less intense, attendant on violation of duty, which in properly cultivated moral natures rises, in the more serious cases, into shrinking from its impossibility." In other words, our conscience. Lets call it a special feeling; lets call the feeling of moral duty "the essence of conscience". There we have it--the thing that compels us to act according to utilitarian ethic is our conscience. Admittedly, we rarely feel pure duty because we often have competing feelings, interests, and social conditioning running around in our heads that distort this sense of moral duty. But how does pure conscience bind us to a particular course of action (i.e., the 1st principle of utilitarianism)? It binds us because it is "a mass of feeling which must be broken through in order to do what violates our standard of right, and which if we do nevertheless violate that standard, will probably have to be encountered afterwards in the form of remorse." In other words, our conscience binds us because we cannot escape it. The obvious objection is that there are people who don't have strong feelings of conscience or are able to ignore their conscience, so how can we say that utilitarianism binds people to action? Mill's (reoccurring) reply is that this is a problem for any ethical system--it is not particular to utilitarianism. Such people can only be compelled to act through external sanctions regardless of what moral system you support. So, I guess this is meant to diffuse the argument that utilitarian ethics should be rejected because it can't bind people to follow it, but neither is it a point in favour of utilitarianism. On the Origins of the Feeling of Duty Mill begins that the origins of the feelings of duty, be they innate or acquired, are unimportant because the net result is the same. Supposing they are innate (here he's implying Kantian ethics), then the feeling of duty would attach to moral principles. But there is no argument to suggest that the innate feeling of duty wouldn't attach to the utilitarian principle rather then, lets say, the categorical imperative. Furthermore, if morality itself is intuitive, it seems that accounting for the effect of our actions on the happiness of others is "intuitively obligatory". So, even if our sense of moral duty is innate (which Mill denies) this is no objection to utilitarianism. Suppose instead, as Mill does, that moral feelings are learned rather than innate. They are something we (hopefully) develop over time with experience and education just as we do with things like the ability to reason, to use language, to play an instrument... Just like any capacity we have, our moral feelings can develop to varying degrees, both positively and negatively. So, even if our moral conscience is acquired rather than innate, there is no reason to suppose it couldn't develop to follow utilitarian principles (amongst all the other possibilities). Then Why Utilitarianism? Finally we learn why our conscience will be receptive to utilitarian principles rather than others. Given that, regardless of the origins of our sense of duty and moral conscience, what arguments are there to suppose the utilitarian ethics is the one true standard? So far we've said that human can be conditioned to attach a sense of moral duty to just about moral principle. Ah! Ha! But you see, the utilitarian principle is special! The is a "powerful natural basis of sentiment for utilitarian morality". You see, once the general happiness is recognized as the ethical standard it will be the basis of this powerful natural sentiment. And that natural oh-so-good feeling is the social feeling of mankind--"the desire to be in unity with our fellow creatures..."; that is, our natural tendency to live as social creatures. It is unnatural for us to live outside of a social context. It's hard to dispute that we are social creatures but some people might reply that our natural tendency toward social living doesn't necessarily entail utilitarianism. An egoist or social contract theorist might say, for example, that social living just means that I have to abide by certain conventions if I want to get out of life what I want but still avoid (external) sanctions. Mill further argues that social living is impossible unless the members regard everyone's interests to be equal. People grow up with the understanding that they have to include the interests of others when/before they act. They learn not to injure others. In instances of cooperation they learn that interests can be mutual and that our own well being is often bound up in that of others. He goes on to paint a very pretty picture: Not only does all strengthening of social ties, and all healthy growth of society, give to each individual a stronger personal interest in practically consulting the welfare of others, it also leads him to identify his feelings more and more with their good, or at least with an even greater degree of practical consideration for it. Under these conditions he will, as a matter of habit, consider the good of others in his actions. Once he has this feeling he will want to demonstrate it, and encourage it in others. And even if he doesn't have utilitarian sentiments, for his own self-interest he will want others to be utilitarians because he will benefit. Before long and by this process the utilitarian meme takes over the society, removing sources of opposition and "leveling those inequalities of legal privilege between individuals or classes". Here's the really interesting thing. In a way Mill was right. Empirical evidence suggests that most people think like utilitarians (however, it varies between cultures and contexts). Also, that in groups where there are strong social ties members do tend to consider the happiness of the other members in their moral calculus. As the intellectual underpinnings and the utilitarian feelings of the individual grow, he will oppose socio-economic and socio-political structures that prevent others from having the benefits he has. Through this mechanism the moral community grows in number. Basically, once you go utilitarian you never go back cuz it just feels sooooo natural. When you accept utilitarianism into your heart it is not as "a law despotically imposed by the power of society, but as an attribute which is would not be well for them to be without". Utilitarianism, once embraced, works in harmony with external or internal motives to care for others. When external sanctions fail to motivate, the utilitarian ethic will provide internal motivation (sense of duty) to consider the happiness of others (in proportion to the extent to which to agent is utilitarian). Sounds nice, doesn't it?
Updayt: Hey er'body...I'm baaack! Before we get down to biniz and talk about Mill an' stuff here's a brief updayt. First, my sincerest apologies to the throngs of my adoring fans that had to go the whole summer without reading a new post, but I needed a break. Also, I was studying for the state and national realtor's license exam (which I successfully passed) as well as doing my usual pants off dance off to make mo' money. The three elements combined to form the perfect trifecta of excuses to not write.
Anyhow, I'm very pleased to announce that I'm only 3 1/2 months away (or 3 term papers and a couple of midterms--as I measure it) from gradulating from koledg with an MA. This semester I'll be taking the following courses/seminars: Classics in the history of ethics (modern history); philosophy of special sciences (i.e., of biology, psychology, neurology); and philosophy of punishment and retribution.
After the first week of classes I get the feeling that this semester is going to be a lot of work. The first two classes require a ton of reading (even more than usual). I'm not really a fan of courses with a ton of reading because usually--since it's often hard enough just to get through it once--I never really get to read it as carefully as I'd like. I get more out of courses where you do close readings of less material but really get to know it... but I digress...
Lets get down to biniz Mill's Utilitarianism Favorite Quote: (vs the idea that humans can't have "happy" lives--Mill disagrees and explains what he means by "happy" life.) "If by happiness be meant a continuity of highly pleasurable excitement, it is evident enough this is impossible [...] Philosophers that teach that happiness is the end of life were fully aware of [this]. The happiness which [utilitarians] meant was not a life of rapture, but moments of such, in an existence made up of few and transitory pains, many and various pleasures, with a foundation of the whole not to expect more from life than it is capable of bestowing. A life thus composed, to those who have been fortunate enough to obtain it, has always appeared worthy of the name of happiness."
Overview of Classical Utilitarianism Ok, lets take a general view of utilitarianism. (Unless otherwise specified, by 'utilitarianism' I mean classical utilitarianism). In the most general/crude terms, utilitarianism is the view that an action is morally right or good to the degree that it produces the maximum amount of happiness for the maximum amount of people. The assumption is that things/actions are good or bad based on their consequences, and happiness as an end is good. Of course, this talk of happiness/utility doesn't mean much unless we define our terms. What do we mean by happiness? Happiness means pleasure and absence of pain; unhappiness is pain and absence of pleasure.
So, if counting blades of grass makes people happy, then is an action 'right' or 'good' if allows the maximum number of people to count blades of grass? Some early utilitarians like Bentham didn't discriminate between sources of pleasure. But this runs into objections pretty quickly. If heroin makes me happy, then is it good? Are drug dealers' actions good? At this point, utilitarians are going to have to refine their view. And that's exactly what Mill tried to do.
In the broadest terms, Mill introduced "qualitative hedonism" (as opposed to quantitative). That is, not all sources of happiness are on par. Some happiness-producing activities/things are better than others. The problem of course is how to measure sources/types of happiness against each other. Who's to say that the pleasure someone derives from eating cheezeburgers is less than the pleasure another derives from listening to opera or solving a math problem. How do we even begin to compare these disparate things? And how do we do it in a non-question-begging way? That is, how do we do a comparison in which the judgments are impartial--by which all the things I think are best don't just happen to be, after my own careful analysis, the ones that really are best?
It's an interesting problem. Think about it for a moment... Can we discriminate between types of pleasure? How?
Well, this overview is turning into more than an overview so lets move on and get into some to the "especifics".
Mill vs Standard Criticisms
Vs The Ranking of Pleasures Problem/Objection: The critics accuse utilitarians of having the "ethics of swine", for if consequent happiness is all it takes to make something right or good, then what's to stop us from enacting policies that allow maximum wallowing in our animal pleasures in the name of goodness? Mill's brand of utilitarianism includes the premise that not all pleasures are equal, but how do we determine that "higher" (intellectual) pleasures have more intrinsic goodness than "lower" (sensual) pleasures?
Mills solution to this problem is summarized by the phrase "better to be a human being dissatisfied than a swine satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied". (I've always loved this line...I still remember it from my very first intro philosophy class.)
Ok, admittedly we can still ax, how do we know this to be true? Well, ax yourself (ouch!), given the choice would you rather be a happy swine rolling in the mud or would you rather be a disgruntled human? I hope you answered the latter--and didn't sustain any serious injuries while axing yourself.
So, if you're not completely convinced, here's the argument: if the fool or the pig disagree with our assessment, it's because they haven't experience both positions. That is, someone who has experienced both types of pleasure, both intellectual and sensual, will agree that the pleasure or happiness experienced from the former is of higher quality. The judgment can only be made by someone who has experienced both.
Someone might reply that, "but sometimes even the most intelligent people succumb to the lower pleasures when they could be reading the latest translation of classical Russian literature." Surely, they know that reading Russian lit. is the higher pleasure. One response to this is that, despite the slip up, the cultured person still knows that the intellectual pleasure is of higher quality.
Besides, I don't think Mill's talking about one-off acts here. He's talking about general ways of living and how to determine what types of policies and actions we should institute--about the activities that should be promoted on a society-wide level. So, an individual who has experienced and is capable of an intellectual life is not going to chose a life purely indulgent in the sensual pleasures and will recognize the greater good (happiness) in the former.
I have to say I find this argument compelling--(if we don't try to get too fine grained about it). Of course this is purely anecdotal so it doesn't really count as empirical evidence in favour of Mill, but in my life I basically had the same choice--and the decision was easy...even if it took me a while!
Another way to look at how to determine what kinds of pleasure are best is from the flip side--that of pain. How do we know which of two things causes more pain? The judgment can only be made by those who have experienced both. Likewise, in determining what types of pleasure are greatest, the judgment can only be made by someone who has experienced both--"or if they differ, that of the majority among them...".
There are a couple of problems with this argument that I'll table for now cuz I want to keep moving...but the quick and dirty problem with Mill's proposal is that if "pleasure" is the thing that makes actions good, then there must be something other than pleasure upon which he makes the distinction between higher and lower quality pleasures. Pleasure is pleasure, just like squareness is squareness or hardness is hardness. To distinguish between 2 square objects one has to be more or less square than the other. Which implies that the difference lies in quantity, not quality. A poor quality square is such because its corners are perhaps rounded. It has less squareness than its higher quality counterpart. Ok, so maybe it's not the best analogy, but I hope you get it. If not, I'll be more specific next post... Vs Virtue as the Source of Moral Goodness Another objection to utilitarianism is that what makes an action (or person) good is virtue rather than consequent happiness. Suppose some noble person voluntarily sacrifices his own happiness for that of others. Clearly, this virtuous act is good. But why is it good? Is it mere self-sacrifice what makes it good? Mill's reply is that we regard this instance of self-sacrifice as good because its consequence was greater happiness. What would we think of self-sacrifice that didn't result in greater happiness for others? That is, the end of the action was not happiness (broadly speaking)? This action would be regarded as silly. So, it is the fact that happiness is produced as a consequence of the act that the action is good.
Again, we needn't only appeal to examples using happiness or pleasure to illustrate the point. We can imagine a case where a hero sacrifices himself or his own absence of suffering so that others may be free of suffering. If his action didn't result in a diminution of pain or suffering for others it would be difficult to see why it is 'good'.
Mill asks, "Would [the sacrifice] be made if the hero or martyr did not believe that it would earn for others immunity from similar sacrifices? Would it be made if he thought that his renunciation of happiness for himself would produce no fruit for any of his fellow creatures, but to make their lot like his and place them also in the condition of persons who have renounced happiness?"
Utilitarians aren't saying that self-sacrifice isn't a good thing, only that it is not intrinsically good. What makes it good is its consequences.
Of course, the Kantian will reply that even if the agents action produced no tangible increase in the happiness of others but he had intended for there to be an increase, then this action would be good. Mills reply is that this confuses the rule of action with the motive. The motive doesn't tell you whether the action was good--it tells you about the character of the agent. The goodness of the action is measured by its consequences.
Alright, that enough for right now...I'll have more soon.